Chap. 1a: Systems Which Regard Virtue As Propriety

Chap. 1: Systems which make Virtue consist in Propriety

 

7.2.5. According to Plato, Aristotle, and Zeno, virtue consists in the propriety of conduct.

 

Plato’s System

7.2.6.

I. In Plato’s system, the soul is considered as a little state or republic composed of three faculties or orders.

 

7.2.7. The first is the judging faculty.

  • It determines:
    • the proper means for attaining any end
    • what ends are fit to be pursued
    • what relative value we should put on each
  • Plato very properly called this faculty ‘reason’.
    • He considered it as having a right to be the governing principle of the whole.
    • Reason is the faculty which lets us judge of:
      • truth and falsehood
      • propriety or impropriety of desires and affections

 

7.2.8.The different passions and appetites are the natural subjects of reason.

  • These passions are so apt to rebel against their master.
  • He reduced these passions to two classes or orders:
    1. The passions founded in the irritable part of the soul.
      • These are founded on pride and resentment.
      • These passions rise from or denote what we commonly call ‘spirit’ or ‘natural fire’.
      • Examples are:
        • ambition
        • animosity
        • the love of honour
        • the dread of shame
        • the desire of victory, superiority, and revenge
    2. Those passions founded on the lustful part of the soul.
      • These are founded in the love of pleasure.
      • It comprehended all:
        • bodily appetites
        • love of ease and security
        • sensual gratifications

 

7.2.9. We rarely break that plan of conduct prescribed by reason.

  • In our cool hours, we laid down that plan to ourselves as the most proper for us to pursue.
  • We break it when prompted by those two sets of passions:
    • the ungovernable ambition and resentment,
    • the importunate solicitations of present ease and pleasure
  • These two sets of passions often mislead us.
  • However, they are still necessary parts of human nature:
    • The first defends us against injuries.
      • It asserts our rank and dignity in the world.
      • It makes us aim at what is noble and honourable.
      • It makes us distinguish those who act in the same manner.
    • The second provides for the support and the necessities of the body.

 

7.2.10. The essential virtue of prudence was placed in the strength, acuteness, and perfection of reason.

  • According to Plato, prudence consisted in a just and clear discernment, founded on general and scientific ideas.
    • The ends of those ideas were proper to be pursued.
    • Its means for attaining them were proper.

 

7.2.11. Under the direction of reason, the irritable passions formed the virtue of fortitude and magnanimity when reason was strong enough to enable them to despise all dangers in the pursuit of what was honourable and noble.

  • According to Plato’s system, these irritable passions had a more generous and noble nature than the lustful passions.
    • On many occasions, they were considered as the auxiliaries of reason.
    • They check and restrain the inferior and brutal appetites.
  • He observed that when the love of pleasure prompts to do what we disapprove of, we:
    • are often angry at ourselves.
    • often become the objects of our own resentment and indignation.
      • The angry part of our nature is then called in to assist the rational against the lustful.

 

7.2.12. The three parts of our nature are

  1. reason
  2. the irritable part
  3. the lustful part
  • The perfect concord of those three is called temperance, good temper, or sobriety and moderation of mind.
  • This happens when reason:
    • approved of the gratification aimed at by the irritable and lustful parts of the soul, and
    • commanded only what the irritable and lustful parts were willing to perform.

 

Justice

7.2.13. According to Plato’s system, justice is the last and greatest of the four cardinal virtues.

  • Justice took place when:
    • reason and the irritable and lustful parts of the mind each confined itself to its proper office without attempting to encroach on the office of others,
    • reason directed and passion obeyed, and
    • each passion:
      • performed its proper duty, and
      • exerted itself towards its proper object:
        • easily and without reluctance, and
        • with the suitable force and energy for what it pursued.
  • Plato called this ‘Justice’, after some of the ancient Pythagoreans.
    • Justice was the complete virtue.
    • It was the perfect propriety of conduct.

 

7.2.14. The word which expresses justice in Greek has several meanings.

  • As far as I know, the same word in all other languages has the same meanings.
    • There must be some natural affinity among those meanings.
    1. In one sense we are said to do justice to our neighbour when we:
      • abstain from doing him any positive harm
      • do not directly hurt him in his person or estate or reputation.
        • This is that justice I mentioned above.
        • Its observance may be extorted by force.
        • Its violation exposes one to punishment.
      • This first sense coincides with what:
        • Aristotle and the Schoolmen call ‘commutative justice’
        • Grotius calls the justitia expletrix
          • It consists in:
            • abstaining from what is another’s, and
            • doing whatever we can with propriety be forced to do.
    2. In a second sense, we are said not to do justice to our neighbour unless we feel all the love, respect, and esteem for him which is suitable to his character, situation, and his connection with ourselves.
      • It is in this sense, we are said to do injustice to a man of merit who is connected with us, even if we abstain from hurting him.
      • If we do not exert to serve him and place him in that situation in which the impartial observer would be pleased to see him.
      • This second sense coincides with what:
        • some have called ‘distributive justice’
        • the justitia attributrix of Grotius
          • It consists in proper beneficence, in:
            • using what is ours
            • using it for the charity or generosity most suitable in our situation
      • In this sense, justice comprehends all the social virtues.
    3. In a third sense, the word ‘justice’ is more extensive than the two mentioned, though very much similar to the second one.
      • As far as I know, this sense also runs through all languages.
      • It this sense, we are said to be unjust when we:
        • do not value any object with that degree of esteem, or
        • pursue any object it with the ardour it deserves or excites, according to the impartial observer
      • We do injustice to a poem or a picture when we do not admire them enough.
      • We do them more than justice when we admire them too much.
      • In the same way, we do injustice to ourselves when we do not give sufficient attention to any object of self-interest.
        • In this sense, ‘justice’ means the same thing with exact and perfect propriety of conduct.
          • It comprehends:
            • commutative and distributive justice
            • every other virtue, of prudence, fortitude, temperance
      • Plato understands justice in this last sense.
        • According to him, justice comprehends the perfection of every virtue.

 

Virtue

7.2.15. Such is Plato’s account on the nature of virtue.

  • According to him, it consists in that state of mind in which every faculty:
    • confines itself within its proper sphere without encroaching upon that of any other
    • performs its proper office with that precise degree of strength and vigour which belongs to it
  • His account coincides with what we have said above on the propriety of conduct.

 

Aristotle’s System

7.2.16.

II.According to Aristotle, virtue consists in the habit of mediocrity according to right reason.

  • According to him, every virtue lies in a middle between two opposite vices.
    • One vice offends from being too much, the other from being too little affected by a particular species of objects.
  • Thus, the virtue of fortitude or courage lies in the middle between the opposite vices of cowardice and of presumptuous rashness.
    • Cowardice offends from being too much.
    • Rashness offends from being too little affected by the objects of fear.
  • Thus the virtue of frugality lies in a middle between avarice and profusion.
    • Avarice consists in an excess, profusion in a defect of the proper attention to the objects of self-interest.
  • In the same way, magnanimity lies in a middle between the excess of arrogance and the defect of pusillanimity.
    • Magnanimity consists in too extravagant, the other in too weak a sentiment of our own worth and dignity.
  • This account of virtue corresponds pretty exactly with what has been said above on the propriety and impropriety of conduct.

 

7.2.17. According to Aristotle, virtue did not so much consist in those moderate and right affections, as in the habit of this moderation.

  • To understand this, virtue may be considered as the quality of an action or as the quality of a person.
  • As the quality of an action, it consists in the reasonable moderation of the affection which causes the action, whether this disposition be habitual or not.
  • As the quality of a person, it consists in the habit of this reasonable moderation.
    • It consists in being the customary and usual disposition of the mind.
  • Thus, the action which proceeds from an occasional fit of generosity is a generous action.
    • But the man who performs it is not necessarily a generous person.
      • Because it may be the only generous action he ever performed.
      • His heart’s motive and disposition may have been quite just and proper.
      • But as this happy mood seems to have been the effect of accidental humour than of anything steady or permanent in his character, it can reflect no great honour on him.
  • When we denominate a character as generous, charitable or virtuous, we mean that that is his usual and customary disposition.
    • Single actions do not prove that he is such.
      • If a single action was enough to stamp a virtue on its performer, the most worthless person might lay claim to all the virtues.
        • Since no man has not acted with prudence, justice, temperance, and fortitude.
    • Single actions reflect very little praise for their performer.
      • But a single vicious action greatly reduces and sometimes destroys altogether our opinion of the performer’s virtue.
      • A single vicious action of this kind shows that:
        • his habits are not perfect
        • his usual behaviour is less dependable than we think.

 

7.2.18.  When Aristotle established virtue to consist in practical habits, he probably had this in view, to oppose Plato’s doctrine.

  • Plato thought that the most perfect virtue alone consisted in just sentiments and reasonable judgments concerning what was fit to be done or to be avoided.
    • According to him, virtue might be considered as a science.
      • He thought that:
        • no man could see clearly and demonstratively what was right and what was wrong, and not act accordingly
        • passion might make us act contrary to doubtful and uncertain opinions, not to plain and evident judgments
  • On the contrary, Aristotle thought that:
    • no conviction of the understanding was capable of getting the better of inveterate habits
    • good morals arose from action, not from knowledge

 

7.2.19.

III. Zeno was the founder of the Stoical doctrine.

  • According to him, every animal was by nature:
    • recommended to its own care
    • endowed with the principle of self-love
      • It causes every animal to preserve its existence and all the parts of its nature, in the best state they were capable of.

 

7.2.20. The self-love of man embraced his:

  • body and all its parts, and
  • mind and all its powers

Self-love desired their preservation and maintenance in their best condition.

  • Therefore, whatever tended to support this state of existence was pointed out to him by nature as fit to be chosen.
    • Whatever tended to destroy it, as fit to be rejected.
  • Health, strength, agility, and ease of body, and the eternal conveniences which promoted these, were naturally pointed out to us as:
    • eligible things
    • things that we should prefer to have than to lack
      • Examples are wealth, power, honours, the respect and the esteem of those we live with.
  • On the other hand, sickness, infirmity, unwieldiness, pain of body, and all the eternal inconveniencies were pointed out as things to be avoided.
    • Examples are poverty, lack of authority, contempt or hatred of those we live with.
  • In each of those two opposite classes, some appeared to be more the objects of choice or rejection, than others in the same class.
    • In the first class:
      • health appeared preferable to strength
      • strength to agility
      • reputation to power
      • power to riches
    • In the second class:
      • sickness was more to be avoided than unwieldiness of body
      • ignominy than poverty
      • poverty than the loss of power
  • Virtue and the propriety of conduct was in choosing and rejecting all objects as nature rendered them the objects of choice or rejection.
    • According to the Stoics, we maintained that perfect conduct by:
      • choosing and rejecting with this just and accurate discernment, and
      • bestowing on every object the precise attention it deserved, according to its place in this natural scale of things.
    • This was what they called:
      • to live consistently
      • to live according to nature
      • to obey those laws and directions which nature, or the Author of nature, prescribed for our conduct.

 

7.2.21. So far, the Stoical idea of propriety and virtue is not very different from that of Aristotle and the ancient Peripatetics.

 

7.2.22. Among those primary objects recommended to us by nature as eligible, was the prosperity of our family, relations, friends, country, mankind, and of the universe in general.

  • Nature also taught us that:
    • as the prosperity of two was preferable to that of one, that of many or of all, must be infinitely more so
    • we ourselves were but one
      • Consequently, wherever our prosperity was inconsistent with the prosperity of the whole, it should yield to the latter.
  • We might be assured that whatever happened tended to the prosperity and perfection of the whole, since all the events in this world are conducted by the providence of a wise, powerful, and good God.
    • Therefore, if we were in poverty, sickness, or any calamity, we should first try our best to rescue ourselves from this disagreeable circumstance, as allowed by justice and our duty to others.
    • But if we found this impossible, we should be satisfied that the universe’s order and perfection required that we should continue in this situation in the meantime.
  • Since the prosperity of the whole should appear preferable to so insignificant a part as ourselves, we should like our situation from that moment.
    • This would maintain our conduct’s complete propriety which makes up the perfection of our nature.
    • If any opportunity of extricating ourselves should arise, it became our duty to embrace it.
      • The order of the universe no longer required our continuance in this situation.
      • The great Director of the world plainly called on us to leave it, by so clearly pointing out the road which we were to follow.
    • It was the same case with the adversity of our relations, our friends, our country.
      • If it were in our power to prevent or end their calamity without violating any more sacred obligation, it was our duty to do so.
      • The propriety of action is the rule which Jupiter gave us to direct our conduct.
        • This rule required us to do this.
    • But if it were out of our power to do either, we should consider this event as the most fortunate which could have happened.
      • Because we might be assured that it tended most to the prosperity and order of the whole.
      • If we were wise and equitable, we should desire this order most of all.
      • It was our own final interest, considered as a part of that whole.
        • The prosperity of the whole should be the principal and sole object of our desire.

 

7.2.23. Epictetus says: ‘How are some things according to our nature, and others contrary to it?

  • It is in how we consider ourselves as separated from all other things.
    • For it is according to the nature of the foot to be always clean.
    • But if you consider it as a foot and not as something detached from the body, it must sometimes:
      • trample in the dirt,
      • tread on thorns,
      • be cut off for the sake of the whole body
    • If it refuses this, it is no longer a foot.
    • Thus we should also conceive with regard to ourselves.
  • What are you?
    • A human.
    • If you consider yourself as something separated and detached, it is agreeable to your nature to:
      • live to old age,
      • be rich,
      • be healthy.
    • But if you consider yourself as a man, as a part of a whole, sometimes you must:
      • be sick,
      • be exposed to the inconveniency of a sea voyage,
      • be in want, and
      • perhaps, finally, die before your time.
  • Why then do you complain?
    • Do not you know that by complaining, as the foot ceases to be a foot, so you cease to be a human?’

 

7.2.24. A wise man never complains of Providence’s destiny.

  • He does not think that the universe in confusion when he is out of order.
  • He does not look on himself as a whole, separated and detached from every part of nature, to be taken care of by itself and for itself.
  • He regards himself as how he imagines the great genius of human nature and the world regards him.
  • He enters into the sentiments of that divine Being.
  • He considers himself as an atom and particle of an immense and infinite system.
    • It must and should be disposed of according to the convenience of the whole.
  • Assured of the wisdom which directs all the events of human life, he accepts whatever lot befalls him with joy.
    • He is satisfied that, if he had known all the connections and dependencies of the parts of the universe, he would have wished the very lot himself.
    • If it is life, he is contented to live.
    • If it is death, he willingly goes where he is appointed.
      • Since nature must not need his presence here.
  • A cynical philosopher had doctrines the same as those of the Stoics.
    • He said:
      • ‘I accept, with equal joy and satisfaction, whatever fortune can befall me.
      • Riches or poverty, pleasure or pain, health or sickness, all is alike.
      • Nor would I desire that the Gods should change my destination in any respect.
      • If I should ask of them anything beyond what their bounty has already bestowed, it would be that they inform me beforehand what they wanted to do with me.
        • So that I can voluntarily:
          • place myself in this situation
          • demonstrate my cheerfulness in embracing their allotment
  • Epictetus says:
    • ‘If I am going to sail, I choose the best ship and the best pilot.
    • I wait for the fairest weather that my circumstances and duty will allow.
    • Prudence and propriety are the principles which the Gods have given me to direct my conduct.
      • They require only this of me.
      • But if a storm arises, which the vessel nor the pilot could withstand, I give myself no trouble about the consequence.
      • All that I had to do is done already.
      • The directors of my conduct never command me to be miserable, anxious, desponding, or afraid.
      • Whether we are to be drowned or come to a harbour, is the business of Jupiter, not mine.
      • I leave it entirely to his determination, nor ever break my rest considering how he is likely to decide it.
      • I receive whatever comes with equal indifference and security.

 

7.2.25. To the Stoical wise man, all the events of human life must be indifferent, because of:

  • this perfect confidence in that benevolent wisdom which governs the universe
  • this entire resignation to whatever order that wisdom might think proper to establish.

His happiness consisted altogether in:

  1. The contemplation of the happiness and perfection of:
    • the great system of the universe
    • the good government of:
      • the great republic of Gods and men
      • all rational and sensible beings
  2. Discharging his duty, in acting properly in the affairs of this great republic whatever little part that wisdom had assigned to him.
    • The propriety or impropriety of his endeavours might be of great consequence to him.
    • Their success or disappointment could be of none at all.
    • It could excite no passionate joy or sorrow, no passionate desire or aversion.
    • If he preferred some events to others, it was not because he:
      • regarded the one as better than the other, or
      • thought that his own happiness would be more complete in the fortunate than in the distressful situation
    • It was because the propriety of action required him to choose and reject in this way.
      • This propriety of action was the rule the Gods had given him to direct his conduct.
  • All his affections were absorbed and swallowed up in two great affections:
    1. His affection for the discharge of his own duty
    2. His affection for the greatest possible happiness of all rational and sensible beings
      • For this gratification, he rested with the perfect security on the wisdom and power of the great Superintendant of the universe.
  • His sole anxiety was about:
    • the gratification of the discharge of his own duty.
    • the propriety of his own endeavours
  • He trusted whatever happened to a superior power and wisdom, to promote that great end which he himself desired most.

 

7.2.26. This propriety of choosing and rejecting was originally introduced, recommended, and pointed out to us by the things chosen and rejected for their own sake.

  • Yet when we became thoroughly acquainted with choosing and rejecting, the actual obtaining of choice or the actual avoidance of rejection necessarily appeared of much less value than:
    • the order, grace, beauty which we discerned in this conduct
    • the happiness which we felt from it
  • From the observation of this propriety arose the happiness and the glory of human nature.
  • From its neglect arose its misery and disgrace.

 

7.2.27. But to a wise man whose passions were perfectly subjected to the ruling principles of his nature, the exact observation of this propriety was equally always easy.

  • If he were in prosperity, he returned thanks to Jupiter for having joined him with circumstances which
    • were easily mastered
    • there was little temptation to do wrong
  • If he were in adversity, he equally returned thanks to the director of this spectacle of human life for giving him a vigorous athlete for an opponent.
    • It made the contest more violent, but the victory more glorious and equally certain.
  • Can there be any shame in that distress which:
    • is not of our fault
    • we behave with perfect propriety?
  • Therefore, there can be no evil.
    • On the contrary, there can be the greatest good and advantage.
  • A brave man exults in those dangers which his fortune has involved him, from no rashness of his own.
    • They afford an opportunity of exercising that heroic intrepidity.
    • Its exertion gives the exalted delight which flows from the consciousness of superior propriety and deserved admiration.
  • One who masters all his exercises is not afraid to measure his strength and activity with the strongest.
    • In the same manner, one who masters all his passions, does not dread any circumstance which the Superintendant of the universe places him in.
  • The bounty of that divine Being has provided him with virtues which render him superior to every situation.
    • If it is pleasure, he has temperance to refrain from it.
    • If it is pain, he has constancy to bear it.
    • If it is danger or death, he has the magnanimity and fortitude to despise it.
  • The events of human life can never find him unprepared or at a loss how to maintain that propriety of conduct.
    • Such propriety constitutes his glory and happiness.

 

7.2.28. The Stoics appear to have considered human life as a game of great skill which had a mixture of chance.

  • In such games, the stake is commonly a trifle.
    • The whole pleasure of the game arises from:
      • playing well,
      • playing fairly, and
      • playing skilfully.
  • If despite all his skill, the good player loses by chance, the loss should be a matter of merriment than of serious sorrow.
    • He has:
      • made no false stroke
      • done nothing which he should be ashamed of
      • completely enjoyed the game’s whole pleasure
  • If the bad player should win despite all his blunders, his success can give him little satisfaction.
    • He is mortified by the memory of all his faults.
    • Even during the play, he can enjoy none of the pleasure it brings.
    • Almost his every stroke is preceded by fear, doubt, and hesitation from ignorance of the rules of the game.
      • When he has played it, the mortification of finding it a gross blunder commonly completes the unpleasing circle of his sensations.
  • According to the Stoics, human life, with all the advantages which can possibly attend it, should be regarded as:
    • a mere two-penny stake, and
    • a matter too insignificant to merit any anxious concern.

 

  • Our only anxious concern should be about the proper method of playing and not about the stake.
    • If we placed our happiness in winning the stake, we placed it in what depended on causes beyond our power and out of our direction.
    • We necessarily exposed ourselves:
      • to perpetual fear and uneasiness
      • frequently to grievous and mortifying disappointments
  • If we placed it in the propriety of our conduct or by playing well, fairly, wisely and skilfully, we placed it in what might be altogether in our own power, through proper discipline, education, and attention.
    • Our happiness was perfectly secure and beyond the reach of fortune.
  • The event of our actions was equally out of our concern, if it was out of our power.
    • We could never:
      • feel fear or anxiety about it
      • suffer any grievous or serious disappointment.

 

7.2.29. They said that human life itself can be the proper object of our choice or our rejection, according to different circumstances.

  • Life was the proper object of choice if there were actually more circumstances agreeable, than contrary, to nature.
    • The propriety of conduct required that we stay alive.
  • On the other hand, if there were actually more circumstances contrary to nature, without any hope of amendment, life itself became the object of rejection, to a wise man.
    • He was free to remove himself out of life.
    • The propriety of conduct required him to do so.
      • This propriety was the rule the Gods gave him to direct his conduct.
  • Epictetus says:
    • ‘I am ordered not to dwell at Nicopolis.
      • I do not dwell there.
    • I am ordered not to dwell at Athens.
      • I do not dwell at Athens.
    • I am ordered not to dwell in Rome.
      • I do not dwell in Rome.
    • I am ordered to dwell in the little and rocky island of Gyarae.
      • I go and dwell there.
    • But the house smokes in Gyarae.
      • If the smoke is moderate, I will bear it, and stay there.
      • If it is excessive, I will go to a house from whence no tyrant can remove me.
    • I keep in mind always that:
      • the door is open
      • I can walk out when I please
      • I can retire to that hospitable house which is open to all the world at all times
    • For beyond my undermost garment, beyond my body, no man living has any power over me.
  • The Stoics said:
    • Walk forth by all means if:
      • your situation is disagreeable on the whole
      • your house smokes too much for you
    • But walk forth without fretting, murmuring, or complaining.
      • Walk forth calmly, contentedly, rejoicingly, returning thanks to the Gods.
    • The Gods from their infinite bounty, have opened the safe and quiet harbour of death.
      • At all times, it is ready to receive us from the stormy ocean of human life.
    • The Gods have prepared this sacred, inviolable, great asylum, always open, always accessible.
      • It is beyond the reach of human rage and injustice.
      • It is large enough to contain all those who wish and all those who do not wish to retire to it.
      • It is an asylum which takes away from every man every pretence of complaining or even of fancying that there can be any evil in human life, except that which he may suffer from his own folly and weakness.

 

7.2.30. In the few fragments of their philosophy which have come down to us, the Stoics sometimes talk of leaving life with a gaiety and even with a levity.

  • This might induce us to believe that they believed that we could, with propriety, leave life wantonly and capriciously, on the slightest disgust or uneasiness.
  • Epictetus says:
    • ‘When you drink with such a person, you complain of his long stories about his Mysian wars.
      • “He says “Now my friend, having told you how I succeeded at such a place, I will tell you how I was besieged in another.”
    • But if you do not want to be troubled with his long stories, do not accept of his supper.
      • If you accept his supper, you cannot complain of his long stories.
    • It is the same case with the evils of human life.
      • Never complain of something which is in your power at all times to get rid of.’
  • However, despite this gaiety and levity of expression, the alternative of leaving life or of remaining in it, was a most serious and important matter of deliberation to the Stoics.
    • We should never leave it until we were distinctly called on to do so by that superintending power which originally placed us in it.
      • But we were to consider ourselves as called on to do so, not merely at the appointed and unavoidable term of human life.
      • Whenever that superintending Power rendered our life the proper object of rejection, the great rule which he had given us for the direction of our conduct required us to leave it.
        • We might then hear the awful and benevolent voice of that divine Being distinctly calling on us to do so.

 

7.2.31. It was on this account that it might be the duty of a wise man to remove out of life though he was perfectly happy.

  • While, on the contrary, it might be the duty of a weak man to remain in it, though he was miserable.
  • If, in the wise man’s situation, there were more circumstances of rejection, the whole situation became the object of rejection.
    • The rule which the Gods had given him for the direction of his conduct, required that he should remove out of it as fast as the circumstances rendered convenient.
    • However, he was perfectly happy even while he remained in it.
    • He had placed his happiness not in:
      • obtaining the objects of his choice, or
      • avoiding the objects of his rejection
    • He always placed his happiness in choosing and rejecting with exact propriety the fitness of his endeavours and exertions, not in its success.
  • If, in the weak man’s situation, there were more circumstances of choice, his whole situation became the proper object of choice.
    • It was his duty to remain in it.
    • However, he was unhappy from not knowing how to use those circumstances.
    • Even if his cards were so good, he did not know how to play them.
      • He could get no real satisfaction on the progress of the game whatever way it turns out.

 

7.2.32. On some occasions, the propriety of voluntary death was perhaps more insisted on by the Stoics than by any other sect of ancient philosophers.

  • However, it was a doctrine common to them all, even to the peaceable and indolent Epicureans.
    • During that age,the founders of all the principal sects of ancient philosophy flourished.
    • During the Peloponnesian war and many years after it ended, all the Greek republics were almost always distracted by the most furious factions at home.
  • Abroad, they were involved in the most sanguinary wars.
    • Each faction sought superiority and the complete destruction of all its enemies, or
    • what was not less cruel, to:
      • reduce them into domestic slavery, the vilest of all states
      • to sell them, man, woman, and child, like herds of cattle, to the highest bidder in the market
  • The smallness of most of those states raised the possibility of them falling into that very calamity which they perhaps inflicted or attempted on their neighbours.
  • In this disorderly state of things, the most perfect innocence, joined to the highest rank and greatest public services, could not secure any man from being condemned to the most cruel punishment of some hostile faction.
    • Even if he was at home and among his own relations and fellow-citizens.
    • He was exposed to greater injuries and insults if:
      • he were taken prisoner in war, or
      • his city was conquered
  • But every man naturally familiarizes his imagination with the distresses he foresees frequently exposed to him.
    • It is impossible that a sailor should not frequently think of:
      • storms and shipwrecks
      • foundering at sea
      • how he will feel and act on such occasions
    • In the same way, it was impossible that a Greek patriot or hero should not familiarize his imagination with all the calamities he is constantly expose to.
  • An American savage:
    • prepares his death-song,
    • considers how to act when he has fallen into the hands of his enemies,
    • is put to death in the most lingering tortures amidst the insults and derision of all the spectators.
  • A Greek patriot or hero could not avoid considering what he should suffer and do:
    • in banishment and captivity,
    • when reduced to slavery,
    • when put to the torture,
    • when brought to the scaffold.
  • But the philosophers of all the sects very justly represented virtue or wise, just, firm, and temperate conduct as the most probable, certain and infallible road to happiness even in this life.
    • However, this conduct could not always exempt.
      • It might even sometimes expose the person to all the calamities during those unsettled times.
    • Therefore, they tried to show that happiness was independent of fortune.
      • The Stoics showed that happiness was independent altogether.
      • The Academic and Peripatetic philosophers showed that happiness was independent in a great measure.
        • Firstly, wise, prudent, and good conduct was the conduct most likely to ensure success in all undertakings.
        • Secondly, if it fails, the mind would not be left without consolation.
          • The virtuous man can still enjoy the complete approbation of his own breast.
          • He can still feel that, no matter how untoward things might have been, all was calm and peace and concord within.
          • He can also generally comfort himself with the assurance that he had the love and esteem of every intelligent and impartial spectator.
            • Those spectators could not fail to admire his conduct and regret his misfortune.

 

7.2.33. Those philosophers tried to show that human life’s greatest misfortunes could be supported more easily than was commonly imagined.

  • They tried to point out the comforts which a man might still enjoy when:
    • reduced to poverty
    • driven into banishment
    • exposed to the injustice of popular clamour
    • labouring under blindness, deafness, in old age, near death
  • They pointed out, too, the considerations which might support his constancy under the agonies of:
    • pain and even of torture
    • sickness
    • sorrow for the loss of children
    • the death of friends and relations, etc.
  • The few fragments which have come down to us of what the ancient philosophers had written on these subjects, form one of the most instructive and most interesting remains of antiquity.
    • The spirit and manhood of their doctrines make a wonderful contrast with the desponding, plaintive, and whining tone of some modern systems.

 

7.2.34. Milton says but while those ancient philosophers suggested every consideration which could arm the hardened breast with stubborn patience, as with triple steel, they laboured above all to convince their followers that:

  • there neither was nor could be any evil in death
  • if their situation became too hard at any time for them to support, the remedy was at hand.
    • The door was open.
    • They could walk out when they pleased, without fear.

They said:

  • if there was no world beyond the present, death could be no evil
  • if there was another world, the Gods must likewise be there
    • A just man could fear no evil while under their protection.

In short, those philosophers prepared a death-song which the Greek patriots and heroes might use on the proper occasions

  • I think it must be acknowledged that of all the sects, the Stoics prepared the most animated and spirited song by far.

Words: 5950

For corrections or comments, please email jddalisay@gmail.com

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s